Introduction

Notes

Math

Epistemology

Search

Andrius Kulikauskas

  • m a t h 4 w i s d o m - g m a i l
  • +370 607 27 665
  • My work is in the Public Domain for all to share freely.

用中文

  • 读物 书 影片 维基百科

Introduction E9F5FC

Questions FFFFC0

Software


Understand category theory concepts in terms of an algebra of requirements.


  • In my philosophy, discover a fruitful way to think about a pair (in the comma category) consisting of an object (in one category) and an arrow (to or from its analogue in a related category).

Requirements are laws. Thus I am describing how laws unfold.

Category theory concepts to describe:

  • Category
  • Functor
  • Natural transformation
  • Limits and colimits
  • Left and right adjoint functors
  • Exact functors

Ideas

  • Consider the nature and importance of universality (for all) and uniqueness (there exists).

The Algebra of Requirements

Laws for objects

  • An object has a unique arrow (the identity morphism) from itself to itself.

Laws for arrows

  • An arrow goes from an object to an object. (Clarification: they may possibly be the same object but not necessarily)

Laws for categories

  • Composition...
  • Equivalence classes of arrows...

A notion of pairing that is weaker than identification. For different arrows may be paired with the same object, yielding different pairs.

Comma category: Given a functor {$G:\mathbf{D}\Rightarrow\mathbf{C}$} and a fixed object {$C$} in {$\mathbf{C}$}

  • Pair an object {$U$} in the pre-category with an arrow {$u$} from {$C$} in the post-category.
  • Pair a morphism {$\tau :U\rightarrow D$} in the pre-category with a composition {$G\tau \circ u = d \circ \textrm{id}_C$} of arrows from {$C$} in the post-category (where we leverage the identity morphism on {$C$}).

Universal mapping property

  • The object (the pair) {$(U,u)$} is an initial object in the comma category {$(C\rightarrow G)$}. Thus for any other object {$(D,d)$} there is a unique morphism {$\tau_d$} in {$\mathbf{D}$} such that {$G\tau_d \circ u = d$}.
  • This means that there is a unique distinction between {$U$} and any other object {$D$}, namely {$G\tau_d$}, which manifests the underlying distinction {$\tau_d$}. Note that we may have {$GU=GD$} but nevertheless {$U\neq D$} so long as {$\textrm{id}_U\neq \tau_d$}.
  • The object {$(U,u)$} is known as a universal morphism from {$C$} to {$G$}.

Left adjoint functor, right adjoint functor

  • A functor {$F:\mathbf{C}\Rightarrow\mathbf{D}$} is a left adjoint functor if for each object {$X$} in {$\mathbf{C}$} there exists a universal morphism {$(G(X),g_X)$} from {$F$} to {$X$}.
  • A functor {$G:\mathbf{D}\Rightarrow\mathbf{C}$} is a right adjoint functor if for each object {$Y$} in {$\mathbf{D}$} there exists a universal morphism {$(F(Y),f_Y)$} from {$Y$} to {$G$}.
Edit - Upload - History - Print - Recent changes
Search:
This page was last changed on September 29, 2020, at 08:31 PM